AIで日本語の学術論文を英訳するー自分の日本語論文を翻訳させてみる(ChatGPT編-その1)

現在のChatGPTにはPDFファイルやWordファイルをアップロードすることができます。

そこでここでは、私が50年前に書いた佐野正博(1983)「物理学における主観と客観の問題」『看護研究』Vol.16 No.3、pp.7-13という論文を英訳させてみた結果を紹介します。

その一覧のやりとりは、下記で見ることができますが、ここでは簡単にその概要を紹介します。
https://chatgpt.com/share/c4ae131b-5b06-46d4-b66a-3f84e0d972c7

PDFファイルをアップロードし、「添付ファイルで私の論文を送ります。英語に翻訳してください。」というプロンプト文を与えた結果は、「ファイルが長いため、内容が一部省略されていますが、提供された内容に基づいて論文の英訳を進めます。まず、主要な見出しと一部の内容を英訳します。」という回答がまずは返ってきました。

これは、「テキスト生成AIにおける最小処理単位「トークン」ーなぜ日本語文よりも英語文の方がより詳細な回答となるのか?」で紹介したように、WEB経由での対話的やりとりでは、1回のプロンプトで与えることができる情報量だけでなく、1回の回答で返される情報量にもかなりの制限があるためです。

 そのため、今回のように長文のPDFファイルに対する回答は、上述のhttps://chatgpt.com/share/c4ae131b-5b06-46d4-b66a-3f84e0d972c7に示したように、「第1ページ目を英語に翻訳してください。」、「第2ページ目を英語に翻訳してください。」、「第3ページ目を英語に翻訳してください。」・・・というように、逐次的にプロンプトを与えることで処理をしました。

なお今回の論文程度の分量であれば。「生成を続ける」というボタンを何度か押す必要がありますが、「英訳の全文を表示してください。」というプロンプト文を与えることで英訳文全体を取得することができます。

その結果は、下記の通りです。なお次のページ「AIで日本語の学術論文を英訳するー自分の日本語論文を翻訳させてみる(ChatGPT編その2)」で、その英訳内容について検討します。

The Problem of Subjectivity and Objectivity in Physics

Masahiro Sano

  1. The Establishment of Objectivity as a Result of Excluding Subjective Elements
Physics is generally considered the most rigorous science, an archetype of an objective and universal science. The practical successes brought about by physics, such as nuclear energy and space exploration, are regarded as proof of the objectivity of physics. The objectivity of physics is guaranteed by its experimental basis and quantitative methods; in other words, it is claimed that physics captures nature as it is through experiments. Because physics is formed from facts derived from experiments without prejudice or preconception, it is considered objective.
Objectivity in physics is understood as capturing the objective reality “as it is,” meaning the exclusion of various subjective elements such as biases and preconceptions. This basis for asserting the objectivity of physics by excluding subjective elements from recognition was provided by Galileo. He believed that “the universe is written in the language of mathematics, and its characters are triangles, circles, and other geometrical figures.” Galileo also distinguished between primary qualities and secondary qualities, considering the latter as subjective elements that should be explained through the former.
As a result, Galileo viewed qualities like “smell, taste, and sound” as secondary qualities that should be excluded from the real world and focused on primary qualities like “size, shape, number, and motion” as the objective properties that should be studied. Thus, discovering the true structure of the physical world and reading the “book of nature” through mathematics became the objective of science according to Galileo. It came to be believed that the objectivity of physics is established as a result of excluding subjective elements.
In this paper, we will examine the problem of subjectivity and objectivity in physics from the second perspective, using the thoughts of physicists themselves as a clue.
 

  1. Subjective Elements Explained Even by Naive Objectivism
In naive objectivism, subjective elements are not completely excluded from the entire process of physical research to maintain objectivity. For example, because physicists are also human, subjective elements such as the motivations for research naturally become one of the elements constituting the research process. There might be physicists who conduct research with thoughts such as “I want to win a Nobel Prize.” Historically, under the leadership of Nazism, there was an attempt to deny relativity theory and quantum mechanics in favor of “Aryan physics.” However, such social motives that physicists may have are external to the content of physics itself and have no direct relevance to the essential research process of physics.
Now, is there no room for subjective elements to enter into physics itself? In reality, this is not the case. Here, I will discuss the issues of hypotheses and the arbitrariness of the expression forms of physical theories, which are subjective elements acknowledged even by naive objectivism.
 
(1) Hypotheses
Since we cannot know a priori what constitutes a correct physical theory or what the objective nature of reality is, it is indispensable to formulate hypotheses in research. That is, “physics without hypotheses” is impossible. For example, Poincaré stated, “Anyone who has reflected a little has noticed how wide a place hypotheses occupy; the mathematician can no more do without them than the experimenter.” Hypotheses are clearly subjective because they are “invented” to explain observed facts rather than being derived from them.
However, hypotheses do not threaten naive objectivism. This is because hypotheses are thought to be immediately tested experimentally, revealing their truth or falsehood. Hypotheses found to be false by experiments are discarded as errors. In contrast, hypotheses proven true are no longer hypotheses but are treated as true, objective theories. Thus, subjective conjectures are ultimately excluded from physics through experimental testing. In naive objectivism, the issue of hypotheses is explained as the process of eliminating subjective elements and establishing objectivity. According to naive objectivism, nature, as a book, is read exactly as it is through experiments, and hypotheses represent subjective motives for which part of nature to read. Like personal motives such as “wanting to win a Nobel Prize,” hypotheses are necessary when starting physical research but are not components of true physical theories as descriptions of nature as it is.
 
(2) The Arbitrariness of the Expression Forms of Theories
With the advancement of mathematization in physics, it has become possible to express physical theories in various forms. For example, the equations of motion in classical mechanics can be expressed in multiple forms, such as Newton’s equation of motion (F = ma), Lagrange’s equations of motion, and Hamilton’s canonical equations. Additionally, space can be represented using three-dimensional Cartesian coordinates (x, y, z) or spherical coordinates (r, θ, φ). Regardless of the expression form used, the same physical theory is being represented due to mathematical equivalence, making it the same physical theory.
In naive objectivism, it is believed that among the various expression forms of a theory, one represents nature as it is, while the others are considered mathematical constructs used for computational convenience. For instance, in classical mechanics, Newton’s equations of motion are generally thought to represent nature as it is. Therefore, according to naive objectivism, the arbitrariness of the expression forms does not negate the fact that the physical theory represents nature as it is.
In practice, there are cases where it is not immediately understood that the theories are the same. This was the case with the two formulations of quantum mechanics: “matrix mechanics” and “wave mechanics.” Due to differences in the underlying concepts of nature and a lack of understanding of their mathematical equivalence, they were initially considered opposing theories. Naive objectivism would explain this as a temporary misunderstanding by physicists. Schrödinger proved the mathematical equivalence of both formulations, resolving this misunderstanding.
However, does mathematical equivalence truly mean the theories are identical as physical theories? The naive objectivist interpretation of physical theories runs into difficulties when answering this question affirmatively. Let’s take electromagnetism as an example to examine this point.
Electromagnetism can be expressed using the electric field (E) and the magnetic field (H) as fundamental physical quantities or using the electromagnetic potentials (A) and (φ) as fundamental physical quantities. Both systems are mathematically equivalent and are considered the same theory. However, since the theoretical concepts that form the basis of both systems differ, they cannot both be considered a description of nature as it is. The claim that the same physical object can be both an electromagnetic field and an electromagnetic potential is contradictory. Thus, according to naive objectivism, one of the systems represents nature as it is, while the other is a mathematical tool. Just as in classical mechanics, where quantities like force, mass, and acceleration are considered real, and the “generalized coordinates” and “generalized forces” in the Lagrangian equations are considered mathematical constructs, the same applies here.
Generally, the electric and magnetic fields are considered real theoretical concepts, while the electromagnetic potential is regarded as a non-existent mathematical construct. This is because the electromagnetic field was considered an observable quantity, whereas the electromagnetic potential was not. However, recently, the quantum effects of electromagnetic potentials (Aharonov-Bohm effect) have been experimentally verified, and electromagnetic potentials are now increasingly considered observable, acknowledging their reality.
As a result, naive objectivism, which regards electromagnetic potentials as mathematical constructs, faces significant difficulties. For the same physical object, two different theoretical concepts can be applied, and both are considered real, leading to a contradiction. If various expression forms of a theory are considered to have equal status, it leads to the denial of naive objectivism.
The negative implications of the arbitrariness of the expression forms of theories against naive objectivism were already pointed out by L. Boltzmann. Evaluating H.R. Hertz’s attempt at a new formulation of classical mechanics, Boltzmann stated, “Hertz has made physicists keenly aware of what philosophers have been saying all along: that no theory can ever be something that actually coincides with nature.”
 
  1. Instrumentalism as a Counter-Ideology to Naive Objectivism
In section 2, I discussed the issues of subjective elements acknowledged even by naive objectivism. However, these subjective characteristics do not completely negate naive objectivism. It is still possible to explain the existence of these elements within the framework of naive objectivism. Therefore, here, I will consider a more systematic critique of naive objectivism.
First, let’s consider instrumentalism, which emerged around the same time as naive objectivism. Instrumentalism regards theoretical concepts merely as tools for calculation and denies their reality.
(1) Instrumentalism — Theories and Theoretical Concepts as Tools for Calculation
Copernicus proposed the heliocentric theory, asserting that the Earth actually revolves around the Sun. In contrast, some critics of the heliocentric theory took the position that it was merely a tool for calculation and not a true description of the world. For example, Andreas Osiander, in the preface to Copernicus’s major work On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres, wrote, “It is not necessary that these hypotheses should be true or even probable; it is sufficient if they provide a calculus consistent with the observations.” This statement criticized the naive objectivist understanding of the heliocentric theory.
Instrumentalism, which positioned physical theories as mathematical tools for calculation and prediction, was inherited by thinkers like Berkeley. Berkeley argued that force “does not actually exist in nature but should be seen as a mathematical hypothesis” and that while it is “useful for reasoning and calculations concerning motion or bodies in motion, it is of no use for understanding the true nature of
motion itself.” He further noted that “regarding gravity, it is clear that Newton did not introduce it as a true physical property but merely as a mathematical hypothesis.” These statements criticized the naive objectivist understanding of Newtonian mechanics.
Instrumentalism continues to be supported by many physicists even today. For example, Schrödinger, one of the founders of wave mechanics, initially regarded the wave function as an existing wave, maintaining a naive objectivist stance. However, he later shifted to an instrumentalist position. In an article titled “The Present Situation in Quantum Mechanics,” Schrödinger stated that with the establishment of quantum mechanics, “one has to abandon naive realism and rely directly on the indubitable proposition that, in the end, there is only observation and measurement. Henceforth, all our physical thoughts are fundamentally based on or directed toward the results of measurements that are, in principle, feasible. … The wave function is nothing more than a means to predict the probabilities of measurement outcomes.” This statement reflects an instrumentalist interpretation of quantum mechanics.
Moreover, Dirac, who significantly contributed to the development of quantum mechanics, said, “Physicists know how to calculate and compare the results with experiments. If the results agree with the experiments, they are satisfied, and that’s all physicists need.”
Thus, many modern physicists (especially those researching quantum mechanics) take an instrumentalist stance. Just as the emergence of non-Euclidean geometry in mathematics led to the denial of a naive objectivist understanding of mathematics, the development of quantum mechanics in physics can be seen as having broken naive objectivism. This is because the fundamental concept of quantum mechanics, the wave function, cannot be interpreted as representing an actual wave in nature. There are several reasons why the wave function is considered non-real. The most decisive reason is the probabilistic interpretation of the wave function. Since the wave function represents probabilities, it cannot be considered a real wave. Additionally, for many-particle systems, the wave function is expressed not in three-dimensional space but in multi-dimensional configuration space. Since real space is three-dimensional, the wave function cannot be said to exist within real space. Furthermore, while nature is considered to have a real-number structure, the wave function is expressed in complex numbers, which is another reason.
Quantum mechanics cannot be explained from a naive objectivist perspective. That is, the wave function, the fundamental concept of quantum mechanics, is not considered a description of nature as it is. So, is instrumentalism, which regards the wave function merely as a tool for calculation, correct? Next, I will critically examine the claims of instrumentalism.
(2) Criticism of Instrumentalism
Instrumentalism argues that theoretical concepts are tools for prediction and calculation. However, naive objectivists would likely also accept this. The point of contention between naive objectivism and instrumentalism was whether theories are descriptions of nature as it is. With the advent of quantum mechanics, naive objectivism encountered difficulties on this point. However, this does not mean that the claims of instrumentalism are correct. Instrumentalism argues more than just that theories are not descriptions of nature as it is; it claims that theories are subjective constructs that have no connection to nature.
The claim that theories and theoretical concepts are subjective constructs only makes sense in contrast to the objectivity of observations or measurement results. Theoretical concepts are merely products of thought and are subjective, whereas observations or measurement results are not mere products of thought and are considered objective.
As evident from the previous citations related to instrumentalism—such as “in reality, there is only observation and measurement” or “the only basis for all our physical thoughts is … the results of measurements”—instrumentalism assumes the reality (objectivity) of observations or measurement results. Even Mach, an instrumentalist who denied the reality of atoms by regarding them as “mere symbols of complexes of sensory elements,” stated that “sensory facts are the starting point and goal of all adaptations in the thoughts of a physicist.” Thus, observations or measurement results are considered certain, as something to be explained by theories or theoretical concepts. In other words, the objectivity of observations or measurement results supports the instrumentality of theories and theoretical concepts. The assumption of an absolute separation between theory and observation was used to contrast the objectivity of measurement results with the subjectivity of theories.
However, as argued by N.R. Hanson, observational facts are theory-laden. In other words, observations are guided by theories, and theories underlie observations. There is no such thing as pure observation without theory. At the very least, the observational statements that form the basis of physical theories contain theoretical concepts. Observational results without theoretical concepts are meaningless. For physical theory, for instance, the visual position of a needle in an ammeter itself is not the issue; what matters is what this visual position signifies for the physical theory. In other words, in physics, it is not the “visual position of the needle in the ammeter” but the “value of the electric current” that constitutes the observational result.
Even observable physical quantities like velocity, acceleration, current, and voltage are theoretical concepts. The meanings of these terms are given in relation to theories such as mechanics and electromagnetism. As is evident from this discussion, the absolute separation of observation and theory, which is the fundamental premise of instrumentalism, should be rejected. Since there is no “pure observational fact without theory,” instrumentalism is incorrect.
Furthermore, if we acknowledge the theory-laden nature of observational facts, then both observational facts and theories can be said to have the same existential status. If observational facts are considered real, then theories are also real in the same way. One cannot claim that only theories are subjective constructs. The instrumentalist claim that pianos are real but that the atoms said to compose the pianos are not real is incorrect. As argued by Shozo Omori, “The everyday world of appearances and the world depicted by scientists with atoms, molecules, and electromagnetic fields are one and the same.” “Objects as collections of atoms and perceptual images with colors and smells are actually one and the same thing.” The perceptual description and the physical description overlap. The claim that observational facts and theories have equivalent existential status serves as both a critique of instrumentalism and of naive objectivism. Naive objectivism considers only “primary qualities” like size and motion to be objective, while “secondary qualities” like color and sound are purely subjective. However, if we recognize the theory-laden nature of observational facts or “overlapping depictions,” then “secondary qualities” must also be considered objective in some sense.
Against instrumentalism, I have thus far presented critiques from two perspectives, but there are also various critiques from other perspectives. If instrumentalism is to be rejected, as argued thus far, then a different perspective will be needed for a critique of naive objectivism. Next, I will explore a more general critique of naive objectivism from the perspective of the historical change of theories, rather than its relation to quantum mechanics.
 
  1. Theory Change and the Constancy of Nature
The fact that physics changes historically presents a significant difficulty for naive objectivism. Naive objectivism assumes that nature exists independently of the changes in physical theories. For example, in the transition from the geocentric model to the heliocentric model, nature itself remains unchanged and constant. That is to say, no one claims that “suddenly, the Earth started revolving around the Sun” after the heliocentric model was proposed by Copernicus and established as the true theory. Even in the era of Aristotelian cosmology, it is considered today that the Earth was orbiting the Sun, independent of the theory change from geocentric to heliocentric.
If one takes a naive objectivist stance and argues that physical theories are descriptions of nature as it is, then one must also claim that theories should not change as long as nature remains constant. If nature is unchanging, then the theories describing it should not change either. So, why do theories change historically?
Naive objectivism explains this process of theory change as the rejection of false theories (like the geocentric model) and the acceptance of true theories (like the heliocentric model). However, not all theory changes can be understood as a shift from a false theory to a true one. The historical shift from Newtonian mechanics to relativity theory or from classical mechanics to quantum theory is generally not considered a change from a false theory to a true one. To illustrate this point more concretely, let us consider the debate over the nature of light. Newton proposed the particle theory of light. In contrast, Hooke advocated the wave theory. The debate between the particle theory and the wave theory eventually concluded with the wave theory being accepted, due to experiments such as measuring the speed of light in water. Light was then considered to be a wave. However, in 1905, based on phenomena such as the photoelectric effect, Einstein proposed the quantum theory of light. After the experimental confirmation of the Compton effect, the quantum theory of light was regarded as correct. Once again, light was considered a particle. And then another change occurred: by treating electromagnetic fields quantum mechanically, light came to be seen as “photons.” Although opinions differ on what exactly photons are, they are generally considered to possess both particle-like and wave-like properties. In such cases, the position of naive objectivism, which insists that all prior theories were wrong, is overly simplistic because each preceding theory can be considered correct within certain limits.
Moreover, even if we temporarily accept the naive objectivist explanation for the historical change in theories, this generates even more questions. One issue is why theories that were supposedly false were believed to be true in the first place. For example, why did so many people, for such a long time, consider the geocentric model to be true? Furthermore, how can we be sure that the theories currently regarded as “true” will
not be replaced by new theories? Like the geocentric model, could they not just be “believed to be true” but actually be “false”? It is difficult to answer these doubts logically.
In conclusion, recognizing the historical change of theories suggests that naive objectivism is untenable. Naive objectivism is not only rejected in specific cases, such as the arbitrariness of the expression forms of electromagnetic theory or the non-reality of the wave function in quantum mechanics, but it is also rejected from a general perspective, such as the historical change of theories.
Conclusion
Throughout this paper, we have critically examined two representative ideas concerning the problem of subjectivity and objectivity in physics: naive objectivism and instrumentalism. To summarize, naive objectivism asserts the objectivity of theories as descriptions of nature as it is, while instrumentalism claims the subjectivity of theories as mere tools for calculation. In this paper, we have critiqued naive objectivism from the perspective of the historical change of theories and instrumentalism from the perspective of the theory-laden nature of observational facts.
A new thought that transcends naive objectivism and instrumentalism is being developed through a re-examination of the definitions of subjectivity and objectivity. While this paper has only touched on this suggestively, it will be discussed in detail on another occasion.
References
 
 
  1. For example, Nobuharu Tanji’s “The Problem of Observation in Quantum Mechanics” (Shisou, August 1974 issue) and B. d’Espagnat’s Theory of Observation in Quantum Mechanics (translated by Shigeru Machida, Iwanami Shoten).
  2. The philosophical significance of Galileo’s scientific methodology is discussed in detail in E. Cassirer’s Philosophy and Exact Science (translated by Ken Oba, Kinokuniya Bookstore).
  3. The Assayer problem 6 (Masterpieces of the World Volume 21, “Galileo,” Chuo Koronsha, p. 308).
  4. The Assayer problem 48 (same source, p. 505).
  5. For further details, see A. D. Beyerchen’s Scientists Under Hitler (translated by Keiichi Tsunetomi, Iwanami Shoten).
  6. Regarding the importance of the hypothesis method and its historical development, see Laudan, L. (1981) Science and Hypothesis. Also, the famous phrase “I do not fabricate hypotheses” by Newton is discussed in Masao Watanabe’s “Newton and Hypotheses” (included in Newton’s Light and Shadow, Kyoritsu Shuppan).
  7. Poincaré’s Science and Hypothesis (translated by Isaburo Kono, Iwanami Bunko), p. 13.
  8. C. G. Hempel’s Philosophy of Natural Science (translated by Hiroshi Kurosaki, Baifukan), p. 23.
  9. Popper’s The Logic of Scientific Discovery (translated by Yoshikazu Onuchi and Hiroshi Mori, Hosei University Press), p. 48, p. 54.
  10. For further details on this point, see N.R. Hanson’s “Are Wave Mechanics and Matrix Mechanics Equivalent Theories?” in H. Feigl, G. Maxwell (eds.) Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 401-428.
  11. Feynman, Leighton, and Sands’ The Feynman Lectures on Physics III, Electromagnetism (translated by Tatsuo Miyajima, Iwanami Shoten), p. 196.
  12. Hertz’s Principles of Mechanics (translated by Tomoyoshi Kamikawa, Tokai University Press).
  13. Boltzmann’s “Recent Developments in the Methods of Theoretical Physics” (included in Masterpieces of the World Volume 65, “Modern Science I”), p. 463.
  14. Masterpieces of the World Volume 66, “Modern Science II,” Chuo Koronsha, pp. 376-377.
  15. Dirac, “The Evolution of the Physicist’s Picture of Nature” (included in Science and Mathematics, Blue Backs), p. 49.
  16. There is also a rebuttal to this point arguing that nature is complex. R. Penrose, “Is Nature Complex?” (included in Encyclopedia of the Unknown [1] — The Frontiers of Physical Science, Britannica Japan).
  17. E. Mach’s Analysis of Sensations (translated by Gonojuke Sudo and Wataru Makabe, Hosei University Press), p. 254.
  18. E. Mach, same source, p. 266.
  19. N.R. Hanson’s Patterns of Discovery (translated by Yoichiro Murakami, Kodansha), Perception and Discovery Volumes 1 and 2 (translated by Keiichi Noya and Hiroshi Watanabe, Kinokuniya Bookstore).
  20. K.R. Popper’s Conjectures and Refutations (translated by Takashi Fujimoto, Juro Ishigaki, and Hiroshi Mori, Hosei University Press), p. 184.
  21. Shozo Omori’s The Structure of Knowledge and Learning (Obunsha), p. 12.
  22. Shozo Omori, same source, p. 165.
  23. Shozo Omori, same source, pp. 157-158, and K.R. Popper’s Conjectures and Refutations, p. 185.
  24. For a critique of instrumentalism from another perspective, see Yoichiro Murakami, “Nature and Humans” (included in Modern Science and Philosophy, Yushindo). Especially pp. 236-238, and K.R. Popper’s Conjectures and Refutations, Chapter 3 “Three Views on Knowledge.”
  25. A.F. Chalmers’ What is this thing called Science? (translated by Kiyoshi Takada and Masahiro Sano, Koseisha Koseikaku), p. 194.
The Problem of Subjectivity and Objectivity in Physics
Masahiro Sano
  1. The Establishment of Objectivity as a Result of Excluding Subjective Elements
Physics is generally considered the most rigorous science, an archetype of an objective and universal science. The practical successes brought about by physics, such as nuclear energy and space exploration, are regarded as proof of the objectivity of physics. The objectivity of physics is guaranteed by its experimental basis and quantitative methods; in other words, it is claimed that physics captures nature as it is through experiments. Because physics is formed from facts derived from experiments without prejudice or preconception, it is considered objective.
Objectivity in physics is understood as capturing the objective reality “as it is,” meaning the exclusion of various subjective elements such as biases and preconceptions. This basis for asserting the objectivity of physics by excluding subjective elements from recognition was provided by Galileo. He believed that “the universe is written in the language of mathematics, and its characters are triangles, circles, and other geometrical figures.” Galileo also distinguished between primary qualities and secondary qualities, considering the latter as subjective elements that should be explained through the former.
As a result, Galileo viewed qualities like “smell, taste, and sound” as secondary qualities that should be excluded from the real world and focused on primary qualities like “size, shape, number, and motion” as the objective properties that should be studied. Thus, discovering the true structure of the physical world and reading the “book of nature” through mathematics became the objective of science according to Galileo. It came to be believed that the objectivity of physics is established as a result of excluding subjective elements.
In this paper, we will examine the problem of subjectivity and objectivity in physics from the second perspective, using the thoughts of physicists themselves as a clue.
 
  1. Subjective Elements Explained Even by Naive Objectivism
In naive objectivism, subjective elements are not completely excluded from the entire process of physical research to maintain objectivity. For example, because physicists are also human, subjective elements such as the motivations for research naturally become one of the elements constituting the research process. There might be physicists who conduct research with thoughts such as “I want to win a Nobel Prize.” Historically, under the leadership of Nazism, there was an attempt to deny relativity theory and quantum mechanics in favor of “Aryan physics.” However, such social motives that physicists may have are external to the content of physics itself and have no direct relevance to the essential research process of physics.
Now, is there no room for subjective elements to enter into physics itself? In reality, this is not the case. Here, I will discuss the issues of hypotheses and the arbitrariness of the expression forms of physical theories, which are subjective elements acknowledged even by naive objectivism.
 
(1) Hypotheses
Since we cannot know a priori what constitutes a correct physical theory or what the objective nature of reality is, it is indispensable to formulate hypotheses in research. That is, “physics without hypotheses” is impossible. For example, Poincaré stated, “Anyone who has reflected a little has noticed how wide a place hypotheses occupy; the mathematician can no more do without them than the experimenter.” Hypotheses are clearly subjective because they are “invented” to explain observed facts rather than being derived from them.
However, hypotheses do not threaten naive objectivism. This is because hypotheses are thought to be immediately tested experimentally, revealing their truth or falsehood. Hypotheses found to be false by experiments are discarded as errors. In contrast, hypotheses proven true are no longer hypotheses but are treated as true, objective theories. Thus, subjective conjectures are ultimately excluded from physics through experimental testing. In naive objectivism, the issue of hypotheses is explained as the process of eliminating subjective elements and establishing objectivity. According to naive objectivism, nature, as a book, is read exactly as it is through experiments, and hypotheses represent subjective motives for which part of nature to read. Like personal motives such as “wanting to win a Nobel Prize,” hypotheses are necessary when starting physical research but are not components of true physical theories as descriptions of nature as it is.
 
(2) The Arbitrariness of the Expression Forms of Theories
With the advancement of mathematization in physics, it has become possible to express physical theories in various forms. For example, the equations of motion in classical mechanics can be expressed in multiple forms, such as Newton’s equation of motion (F = ma), Lagrange’s equations of motion, and Hamilton’s canonical equations. Additionally, space can be represented using three-dimensional Cartesian coordinates (x, y, z) or spherical coordinates (r, θ, φ). Regardless of the expression form used, the same physical theory is being represented due to mathematical equivalence, making it the same physical theory.
In naive objectivism, it is believed that among the various expression forms of a theory, one represents nature as it is, while the others are considered mathematical constructs used for computational convenience. For instance, in classical mechanics, Newton’s equations of motion are generally thought to represent nature as it is. Therefore, according to naive objectivism, the arbitrariness of the expression forms does not negate the fact that the physical theory represents nature as it is.
In practice, there are cases where it is not immediately understood that the theories are the same. This was the case with the two formulations of quantum mechanics: “matrix mechanics” and “wave mechanics.” Due to differences in the underlying concepts of nature and a lack of understanding of their mathematical equivalence, they were initially considered opposing theories. Naive objectivism would explain this as a temporary misunderstanding by physicists. Schrödinger proved the mathematical equivalence of both formulations, resolving this misunderstanding.
However, does mathematical equivalence truly mean the theories are identical as physical theories? The naive objectivist interpretation of physical theories runs into difficulties when answering this question affirmatively. Let’s take electromagnetism as an example to examine this point.
Electromagnetism can be expressed using the electric field (E) and the magnetic field (H) as fundamental physical quantities or using the electromagnetic potentials (A) and (φ) as fundamental physical quantities. Both systems are mathematically equivalent and are considered the same theory. However, since the theoretical concepts that form the basis of both systems differ, they cannot both be considered a description of nature as it is. The claim that the same physical object can be both an electromagnetic field and an electromagnetic potential is contradictory. Thus, according to naive objectivism, one of the systems represents nature as it is, while the other is a mathematical tool. Just as in classical mechanics, where quantities like force, mass, and acceleration are considered real, and the “generalized coordinates” and “generalized forces” in the Lagrangian equations are considered mathematical constructs, the same applies here.
Generally, the electric and magnetic fields are considered real theoretical concepts, while the electromagnetic potential is regarded as a non-existent mathematical construct. This is because the electromagnetic field was considered an observable quantity, whereas the electromagnetic potential was not. However, recently, the quantum effects of electromagnetic potentials (Aharonov-Bohm effect) have been experimentally verified, and electromagnetic potentials are now increasingly considered observable, acknowledging their reality.
As a result, naive objectivism, which regards electromagnetic potentials as mathematical constructs, faces significant difficulties. For the same physical object, two different theoretical concepts can be applied, and both are considered real, leading to a contradiction. If various expression forms of a theory are considered to have equal status, it leads to the denial of naive objectivism.
The negative implications of the arbitrariness of the expression forms of theories against naive objectivism were already pointed out by L. Boltzmann. Evaluating H.R. Hertz’s attempt at a new formulation of classical mechanics, Boltzmann stated, “Hertz has made physicists keenly aware of what philosophers have been saying all along: that no theory can ever be something that actually coincides with nature.”
 
  1. Instrumentalism as a Counter-Ideology to Naive Objectivism
In section 2, I discussed the issues of subjective elements acknowledged even by naive objectivism. However, these subjective characteristics do not completely negate naive objectivism. It is still possible to explain the existence of these elements within the framework of naive objectivism. Therefore, here, I will consider a more systematic critique of naive objectivism.
First, let’s consider instrumentalism, which emerged around the same time as naive objectivism. Instrumentalism regards theoretical concepts merely as tools for calculation and denies their reality.
(1) Instrumentalism — Theories and Theoretical Concepts as Tools for Calculation
Copernicus proposed the heliocentric theory, asserting that the Earth actually revolves around the Sun. In contrast, some critics of the heliocentric theory took the position that it was merely a tool for calculation and not a true description of the world. For example, Andreas Osiander, in the preface to Copernicus’s major work On the Revolutions of the Heavenly Spheres, wrote, “It is not necessary that these hypotheses should be true or even probable; it is sufficient if they provide a calculus consistent with the observations.” This statement criticized the naive objectivist understanding of the heliocentric theory.
Instrumentalism, which positioned physical theories as mathematical tools for calculation and prediction, was inherited by thinkers like Berkeley. Berkeley argued that force “does not actually exist in nature but should be seen as a mathematical hypothesis” and that while it is “useful for reasoning and calculations concerning motion or bodies in motion, it is of no use for understanding the true nature of
motion itself.” He further noted that “regarding gravity, it is clear that Newton did not introduce it as a true physical property but merely as a mathematical hypothesis.” These statements criticized the naive objectivist understanding of Newtonian mechanics.
Instrumentalism continues to be supported by many physicists even today. For example, Schrödinger, one of the founders of wave mechanics, initially regarded the wave function as an existing wave, maintaining a naive objectivist stance. However, he later shifted to an instrumentalist position. In an article titled “The Present Situation in Quantum Mechanics,” Schrödinger stated that with the establishment of quantum mechanics, “one has to abandon naive realism and rely directly on the indubitable proposition that, in the end, there is only observation and measurement. Henceforth, all our physical thoughts are fundamentally based on or directed toward the results of measurements that are, in principle, feasible. … The wave function is nothing more than a means to predict the probabilities of measurement outcomes.” This statement reflects an instrumentalist interpretation of quantum mechanics.
Moreover, Dirac, who significantly contributed to the development of quantum mechanics, said, “Physicists know how to calculate and compare the results with experiments. If the results agree with the experiments, they are satisfied, and that’s all physicists need.”
Thus, many modern physicists (especially those researching quantum mechanics) take an instrumentalist stance. Just as the emergence of non-Euclidean geometry in mathematics led to the denial of a naive objectivist understanding of mathematics, the development of quantum mechanics in physics can be seen as having broken naive objectivism. This is because the fundamental concept of quantum mechanics, the wave function, cannot be interpreted as representing an actual wave in nature. There are several reasons why the wave function is considered non-real. The most decisive reason is the probabilistic interpretation of the wave function. Since the wave function represents probabilities, it cannot be considered a real wave. Additionally, for many-particle systems, the wave function is expressed not in three-dimensional space but in multi-dimensional configuration space. Since real space is three-dimensional, the wave function cannot be said to exist within real space. Furthermore, while nature is considered to have a real-number structure, the wave function is expressed in complex numbers, which is another reason.
Quantum mechanics cannot be explained from a naive objectivist perspective. That is, the wave function, the fundamental concept of quantum mechanics, is not considered a description of nature as it is. So, is instrumentalism, which regards the wave function merely as a tool for calculation, correct? Next, I will critically examine the claims of instrumentalism.
(2) Criticism of Instrumentalism
Instrumentalism argues that theoretical concepts are tools for prediction and calculation. However, naive objectivists would likely also accept this. The point of contention between naive objectivism and instrumentalism was whether theories are descriptions of nature as it is. With the advent of quantum mechanics, naive objectivism encountered difficulties on this point. However, this does not mean that the claims of instrumentalism are correct. Instrumentalism argues more than just that theories are not descriptions of nature as it is; it claims that theories are subjective constructs that have no connection to nature.
The claim that theories and theoretical concepts are subjective constructs only makes sense in contrast to the objectivity of observations or measurement results. Theoretical concepts are merely products of thought and are subjective, whereas observations or measurement results are not mere products of thought and are considered objective.
As evident from the previous citations related to instrumentalism—such as “in reality, there is only observation and measurement” or “the only basis for all our physical thoughts is … the results of measurements”—instrumentalism assumes the reality (objectivity) of observations or measurement results. Even Mach, an instrumentalist who denied the reality of atoms by regarding them as “mere symbols of complexes of sensory elements,” stated that “sensory facts are the starting point and goal of all adaptations in the thoughts of a physicist.” Thus, observations or measurement results are considered certain, as something to be explained by theories or theoretical concepts. In other words, the objectivity of observations or measurement results supports the instrumentality of theories and theoretical concepts. The assumption of an absolute separation between theory and observation was used to contrast the objectivity of measurement results with the subjectivity of theories.
However, as argued by N.R. Hanson, observational facts are theory-laden. In other words, observations are guided by theories, and theories underlie observations. There is no such thing as pure observation without theory. At the very least, the observational statements that form the basis of physical theories contain theoretical concepts. Observational results without theoretical concepts are meaningless. For physical theory, for instance, the visual position of a needle in an ammeter itself is not the issue; what matters is what this visual position signifies for the physical theory. In other words, in physics, it is not the “visual position of the needle in the ammeter” but the “value of the electric current” that constitutes the observational result.
Even observable physical quantities like velocity, acceleration, current, and voltage are theoretical concepts. The meanings of these terms are given in relation to theories such as mechanics and electromagnetism. As is evident from this discussion, the absolute separation of observation and theory, which is the fundamental premise of instrumentalism, should be rejected. Since there is no “pure observational fact without theory,” instrumentalism is incorrect.
Furthermore, if we acknowledge the theory-laden nature of observational facts, then both observational facts and theories can be said to have the same existential status. If observational facts are considered real, then theories are also real in the same way. One cannot claim that only theories are subjective constructs. The instrumentalist claim that pianos are real but that the atoms said to compose the pianos are not real is incorrect. As argued by Shozo Omori, “The everyday world of appearances and the world depicted by scientists with atoms, molecules, and electromagnetic fields are one and the same.” “Objects as collections of atoms and perceptual images with colors and smells are actually one and the same thing.” The perceptual description and the physical description overlap. The claim that observational facts and theories have equivalent existential status serves as both a critique of instrumentalism and of naive objectivism. Naive objectivism considers only “primary qualities” like size and motion to be objective, while “secondary qualities” like color and sound are purely subjective. However, if we recognize the theory-laden nature of observational facts or “overlapping depictions,” then “secondary qualities” must also be considered objective in some sense.
Against instrumentalism, I have thus far presented critiques from two perspectives, but there are also various critiques from other perspectives. If instrumentalism is to be rejected, as argued thus far, then a different perspective will be needed for a critique of naive objectivism. Next, I will explore a more general critique of naive objectivism from the perspective of the historical change of theories, rather than its relation to quantum mechanics.
 
  1. Theory Change and the Constancy of Nature
The fact that physics changes historically presents a significant difficulty for naive objectivism. Naive objectivism assumes that nature exists independently of the changes in physical theories. For example, in the transition from the geocentric model to the heliocentric model, nature itself remains unchanged and constant. That is to say, no one claims that “suddenly, the Earth started revolving around the Sun” after the heliocentric model was proposed by Copernicus and established as the true theory. Even in the era of Aristotelian cosmology, it is considered today that the Earth was orbiting the Sun, independent of the theory change from geocentric to heliocentric.
If one takes a naive objectivist stance and argues that physical theories are descriptions of nature as it is, then one must also claim that theories should not change as long as nature remains constant. If nature is unchanging, then the theories describing it should not change either. So, why do theories change historically?
Naive objectivism explains this process of theory change as the rejection of false theories (like the geocentric model) and the acceptance of true theories (like the heliocentric model). However, not all theory changes can be understood as a shift from a false theory to a true one. The historical shift from Newtonian mechanics to relativity theory or from classical mechanics to quantum theory is generally not considered a change from a false theory to a true one. To illustrate this point more concretely, let us consider the debate over the nature of light. Newton proposed the particle theory of light. In contrast, Hooke advocated the wave theory. The debate between the particle theory and the wave theory eventually concluded with the wave theory being accepted, due to experiments such as measuring the speed of light in water. Light was then considered to be a wave. However, in 1905, based on phenomena such as the photoelectric effect, Einstein proposed the quantum theory of light. After the experimental confirmation of the Compton effect, the quantum theory of light was regarded as correct. Once again, light was considered a particle. And then another change occurred: by treating electromagnetic fields quantum mechanically, light came to be seen as “photons.” Although opinions differ on what exactly photons are, they are generally considered to possess both particle-like and wave-like properties. In such cases, the position of naive objectivism, which insists that all prior theories were wrong, is overly simplistic because each preceding theory can be considered correct within certain limits.
Moreover, even if we temporarily accept the naive objectivist explanation for the historical change in theories, this generates even more questions. One issue is why theories that were supposedly false were believed to be true in the first place. For example, why did so many people, for such a long time, consider the geocentric model to be true? Furthermore, how can we be sure that the theories currently regarded as “true” will
not be replaced by new theories? Like the geocentric model, could they not just be “believed to be true” but actually be “false”? It is difficult to answer these doubts logically.
In conclusion, recognizing the historical change of theories suggests that naive objectivism is untenable. Naive objectivism is not only rejected in specific cases, such as the arbitrariness of the expression forms of electromagnetic theory or the non-reality of the wave function in quantum mechanics, but it is also rejected from a general perspective, such as the historical change of theories.
Conclusion
Throughout this paper, we have critically examined two representative ideas concerning the problem of subjectivity and objectivity in physics: naive objectivism and instrumentalism. To summarize, naive objectivism asserts the objectivity of theories as descriptions of nature as it is, while instrumentalism claims the subjectivity of theories as mere tools for calculation. In this paper, we have critiqued naive objectivism from the perspective of the historical change of theories and instrumentalism from the perspective of the theory-laden nature of observational facts.
A new thought that transcends naive objectivism and instrumentalism is being developed through a re-examination of the definitions of subjectivity and objectivity. While this paper has only touched on this suggestively, it will be discussed in detail on another occasion.
References
 
 
  1. For example, Nobuharu Tanji’s “The Problem of Observation in Quantum Mechanics” (Shisou, August 1974 issue) and B. d’Espagnat’s Theory of Observation in Quantum Mechanics (translated by Shigeru Machida, Iwanami Shoten).
  2. The philosophical significance of Galileo’s scientific methodology is discussed in detail in E. Cassirer’s Philosophy and Exact Science (translated by Ken Oba, Kinokuniya Bookstore).
  3. The Assayer problem 6 (Masterpieces of the World Volume 21, “Galileo,” Chuo Koronsha, p. 308).
  4. The Assayer problem 48 (same source, p. 505).
  5. For further details, see A. D. Beyerchen’s Scientists Under Hitler (translated by Keiichi Tsunetomi, Iwanami Shoten).
  6. Regarding the importance of the hypothesis method and its historical development, see Laudan, L. (1981) Science and Hypothesis. Also, the famous phrase “I do not fabricate hypotheses” by Newton is discussed in Masao Watanabe’s “Newton and Hypotheses” (included in Newton’s Light and Shadow, Kyoritsu Shuppan).
  7. Poincaré’s Science and Hypothesis (translated by Isaburo Kono, Iwanami Bunko), p. 13.
  8. C. G. Hempel’s Philosophy of Natural Science (translated by Hiroshi Kurosaki, Baifukan), p. 23.
  9. Popper’s The Logic of Scientific Discovery (translated by Yoshikazu Onuchi and Hiroshi Mori, Hosei University Press), p. 48, p. 54.
  10. For further details on this point, see N.R. Hanson’s “Are Wave Mechanics and Matrix Mechanics Equivalent Theories?” in H. Feigl, G. Maxwell (eds.) Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science, pp. 401-428.
  11. Feynman, Leighton, and Sands’ The Feynman Lectures on Physics III, Electromagnetism (translated by Tatsuo Miyajima, Iwanami Shoten), p. 196.
  12. Hertz’s Principles of Mechanics (translated by Tomoyoshi Kamikawa, Tokai University Press).
  13. Boltzmann’s “Recent Developments in the Methods of Theoretical Physics” (included in Masterpieces of the World Volume 65, “Modern Science I”), p. 463.
  14. Masterpieces of the World Volume 66, “Modern Science II,” Chuo Koronsha, pp. 376-377.
  15. Dirac, “The Evolution of the Physicist’s Picture of Nature” (included in Science and Mathematics, Blue Backs), p. 49.
  16. There is also a rebuttal to this point arguing that nature is complex. R. Penrose, “Is Nature Complex?” (included in Encyclopedia of the Unknown [1] — The Frontiers of Physical Science, Britannica Japan).
  17. E. Mach’s Analysis of Sensations (translated by Gonojuke Sudo and Wataru Makabe, Hosei University Press), p. 254.
  18. E. Mach, same source, p. 266.
  19. N.R. Hanson’s Patterns of Discovery (translated by Yoichiro Murakami, Kodansha), Perception and Discovery Volumes 1 and 2 (translated by Keiichi Noya and Hiroshi Watanabe, Kinokuniya Bookstore).
  20. K.R. Popper’s Conjectures and Refutations (translated by Takashi Fujimoto, Juro Ishigaki, and Hiroshi Mori, Hosei University Press), p. 184.
  21. Shozo Omori’s The Structure of Knowledge and Learning (Obunsha), p. 12.
  22. Shozo Omori, same source, p. 165.
  23. Shozo Omori, same source, pp. 157-158, and K.R. Popper’s Conjectures and Refutations, p. 185.
  24. For a critique of instrumentalism from another perspective, see Yoichiro Murakami, “Nature and Humans” (included in Modern Science and Philosophy, Yushindo). Especially pp. 236-238, and K.R. Popper’s Conjectures and Refutations, Chapter 3 “Three Views on Knowledge.”
  25. A.F. Chalmers’ What is this thing called Science? (translated by Kiyoshi Takada and Masahiro Sano, Koseisha Koseikaku), p. 194.
カテゴリー: 未分類 | コメントする

生成AIによるレポート作成(その2-2)-課題に基づく内容構成の検討(Perplexity AI-GPT4o編2)

Perplexity AIは、2024/6/29現在、日本語プロンプト文に対して、基本的には日本語で書かれた資料を用いる設計にデフォルトではなっているようです。

英語で書かれた資料を探したい場合には、「英語で書かれた参考資料を教えて下さい。」といった追加のプロンプト文を与える必要があります。そのように指定すると、下記に示したように数多くの有益な英語資料の情報を得ることができます。

なおPerplexity AIの場合には、ChatGPTとは異なり、実在するWEB情報を返すようになっています。

参考資料のWEB情報に関して、Perplexity AIの回答内容のクリップボード経由でのコピーで直接的に得ることができるのは残念ながら現時点ではURL部分だけです。
 そのため下記の紹介に当たっては、GoogleスプレッドシートのIMPORTXML関数を用いてWEBタイトルを取得しました。すなわち、Googleスプレッドシートのセルに、=IMPORTXML(××,”//title”)[××の部分は、URL情報が記載されたセルを参照している]という記述をすることでWEBページの情報を取得しています。ただしPDFファイルなど一部のURLに関しては、そうした方法で適切なタイトル情報を取得できないため、手作業で入れています。

Perplexity AI-GPT4o版による回答例


https://www.perplexity.ai/search/yuan-zi-li-noshe-hui-de-li-yon-.TtaEmnQSz2SMIoHB4FnBQ#1

原子力の社会的利用に関する推進論と批判論の歴史的展開について英語で書かれた参考資料をいくつか紹介します。

  1. Nuclear Power Debate – Wikipedia:

    • このページでは、原子力発電のリスクと利益に関する長年の議論について詳述されています。特に1970年代と1980年代に議論がピークに達し、2010年代には気候変動に対する意識の高まりとともに再び議論が活発化したことが述べられています[1]。
     
  2. Nuclear Energy in Europe: Who is for and against it and why? – Euronews:

    • ヨーロッパにおける原子力エネルギーの支持者と反対者についての詳細な分析が提供されています。福島事故以降のヨーロッパの状況や、各国の原子力エネルギーに対する立場が説明されています[2]。
     
  3. Literature Review on Public Acceptance of Nuclear Energy – Bulletin of Chinese Academy of Sciences:

    • 原子力エネルギーに対する公衆の受容に関する文献レビューが行われています。特に中国と海外の研究を統合し、既存の研究のギャップと今後の研究方向について議論しています[3]。
     
  4. The Nuclear Debate – World Nuclear Association:

    • 原子力発電の利点と課題についての包括的な議論が行われています。気候変動対策としての原子力の役割や経済的な側面、安全性についても触れられています[5]。
     
  5. Advantages and Challenges of Nuclear Energy – U.S. Department of Energy:

    • 原子力エネルギーの主な利点と現在の課題についての概要が提供されています。特にクリーンエネルギー源としての役割や、雇用創出、国家安全保障への貢献について述べられています[17]。
     

これらの資料を参考にすることで、原子力の社会的利用に関する推進論と批判論の歴史的展開についての理解を深めることができます。

Citations:

[1] Nuclear power debate – Wikipedia
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Nuclear_power_debate
[2] Rizvi,O.(2023)”Nuclear energy in Europe: Who is for and against it and why?” 2023 /12/23
https://www.euronews.com/business/2023/12/23/nuclear-energy-in-europe-who-is-for-and-against-it-and-why
[3] Juan、D., Xufeng,Z. “Literature Review on Public Acceptance of Nuclear Energy: Research Out”
https://bulletinofcas.researchcommons.org/journal/vol34/iss6/8/
[4] Wachtel, I.(2023) “Nuclear Power as a Clean Energy Solution? The Debate Heats Up” USC Dornsife Magazine, 2023/6/15
https://dornsife.usc.edu/magazine/2023/06/the-nuclear-debate/
[5] The Nuclear Debate – World Nuclear Association
https://world-nuclear.org/information-library/current-and-future-generation/the-nuclear-debate
[6] Bonev, P. et al. (2024) “Nuclear waste in my backyard: Social acceptance and economic incentives,” Energy Policy,185(February 2024)
https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/S0301421523005645
[7] “Q&A: Public Opinion of Nuclear and Why it Matters to the Clean Energy Transition | IAEA”
https://www.iaea.org/newscenter/news/qa-public-opinion-of-nuclear-and-why-it-matters-to-the-clean-energy-transition
[8] The Arguments For and Against Nuclear Energy – ASU Prep Digital
https://www.asuprepdigital.org/student_blog/the-arguments-for-and-against-nuclear-energy/?seq_no=3
[9] “Sustainability | Free Full-Text | How Social Impressions Affect Public Acceptance of Nuclear Energy: A Case Study in China”
https://www.mdpi.com/2071-1050/14/18/11190
[10] The Nuclear Debate
https://www.futurelearn.com/info/courses/climate-change-the-solutions/0/steps/121526
[11] 10 Reasons to Oppose Nuclear Energy | Green America
https://greenamerica.org/fight-dirty-energy/amazon-build-cleaner-cloud/10-reasons-oppose-nuclear-energy
[12] “The Social Acceptance Challenge,” National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. (2023) Laying the Foundation for New and Advanced Nuclear Reactors in the United States. Washington, DC: The National Academies Press. Chapter: 8
https://nap.nationalacademies.org/read/26630/chapter/10
[13] “Stewart Brand + Mark Z. Jacobson: Debate: Does the world need nuclear energy? | TED Talk”TED2010, February 2010
https://www.ted.com/talks/stewart_brand_mark_z_jacobson_debate_does_the_world_need_nuclear_energy/transcript
[14] Char,N.L., Csik, B.J. (1987) “Nuclear power development:History and outlook – Events have changed the global prospects for nuclear power,” IAEA BULLETIN, 3/1987, pp.19-25
https://www.iaea.org/sites/default/files/publications/magazines/bulletin/bull29-3/29304781925.pdf
[15] Čábelková,I. (2021) “The social acceptance of nuclear fusion for decision making towards carbon free circular economy: Evidence from Czech Republic” Technological Forecasting and Social Change, 163,
https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/abs/pii/S0040162520313032
[16] BBC Learning English – 6 Minute English / How green is nuclear energy?
https://www.bbc.co.uk/learningenglish/english/features/6-minute-english/ep-211125
[17] Advantages and Challenges of Nuclear Energy | Department of Energy
https://www.energy.gov/ne/articles/advantages-and-challenges-nuclear-energy
[18] “How Social Impressions Affect Public Acceptance of Nuclear Energy: A Case Study in China”
https://www.researchgate.net/publication/363402070_How_Social_Impressions_Affect_Public_Acceptance_of_Nuclear_Energy_A_Case_Study_in_China
[19] Lesson Plan | Nuclear Energy: What’s Your Reaction?
https://www.calacademy.org/educators/lesson-plans/nuclear-energy-whats-your-reaction
[20] “7 reasons why nuclear energy is not the answer to solve climate change | One Earth”
https://www.oneearth.org/the-7-reasons-why-nuclear-energy-is-not-the-answer-to-solve-climate-change/

Perplexity AIにおける参考資料表示画面
Perplexity AIは、他のテキスト生成AIとは異なり、回答の生成に用いた資料を下記の図のような形で別表示できる点で優れています。ただし大変に残念なことに、この別表示画面の内容を簡単にダウンロードできるような設定になってはいません。

<

カテゴリー: レポート作成, 原子力の平和的利用, 情報検索, 生成AIの利用法, 資料検索 | 1件のコメント

音声マークアップ言語SSML(Speech Synthesis Markup Language)

AI音声読み上げのための細かな指示を、テキスト文でできるようにしたものが音声マークアップ言語SSML(Speech Synthesis Markup Language)です。

SSMLは、Webページの記述言語であるHTML(HyperText Markup Language)と同じように、「開始」タグ(opening tag)と「終了」タグ(closing tag)の組み合わせで記述するスタイルを取っています。

 
  1. SSMLの仕様の詳細は下記WEBページにあります。
     
  2. Google作成のリファレンスが下記WEBページにあります。
    Google 「音声合成マークアップ言語(SSML)」ホーム>Cloud Text-to-Speech API>ドキュメント>リファレンス
    https://cloud.google.com/text-to-speech/docs/ssml?hl=ja

    ただ残念なことに、本リファレンスは、W3Cの仕様詳細のかなりコンパクトな説明です。きめ細かい指示をするためには、W3Cの仕様詳細を読む必要があります。

     
  3. SSMLの詳細は、上記をご覧いただければと思いますが、SSMLを用いることで、読み上げの「ピッチ」(音の高低)、「発話速度」、「音量」などのカスタマイズが可能です。
    1. 例えば、下記のように記述すると、通常より半音2つ分低く、ゆっくりとした読み上げになるとのことです。

       <prosody pitch=”-2st” rate=”slow” >Can you hear me now?</prosody>
       
          pitch=”-2st” が「ピッチ(音の高低)を半音2つ分低くする」指示です。
          rate=”slow” が「ゆっくりと読み上げさせる」指示です。

      なお、 ピッチ(音の高低)、発話速度に関する指示 prosodyの詳細は、
      下記に説明があります。
      https://www.w3.org/TR/speech-synthesis11/#S3.2.4

       
    2. 音量については、相対的指示( 例:”x-low”, “low”, “medium”, “high”, “x-high”)だけでなく、デシベル単位での細かな指示(例:+6.0dB)も可能なようです。
      強調・非強調といった音量に関する指示emphasisの詳細は下記にあります。
      https://www.w3.org/TR/speech-synthesis/#S3.2.2
       

  4. SSMLを用いた音声読み上げ指示の具体例に関して、本サイトでは下記で具体例を紹介しています。
    1. 音声合成マークアップ言語(SSML)の利用例1-日本語による「AIに関するピーターパンとアラレちゃんの仮想対話」
    2. 音声合成マークアップ言語(SSML)の利用例2-英語による「AIに関するピーターパンとアラレちゃんの仮想対話」


上記は生成AIに作成させたイラスト図です。

カテゴリー: TIPS, ピーターパンとアラレちゃんのAIについての討, 文章読み上げ, 音声合成マークアップ言語(SSML) | コメントする

生成AIによるレポート作成(その2)-課題に基づく内容構成の検討(Perplexity AI-GPT4o編)

 ここでも引き続き、レポート作成作業において「生成AIがどの程度まで使えるのか?」「どのように使うと良いのか?」に関して、「原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開」(Historical Development of Arguments for and against Civilian/Non-Military Use of Nuclear power)課題を例に取り、具体的に詳しく見ていくことにしよう。

 

別掲記事で論じているように、生成AIに与えるプロンプト文は必ずしも文章である必要はない。というのも、WEBインターフェースであれ、API経由であれ、生成AIに与えたプロンプト文は、実際に生成AIに処理させる段階でトークン(token)≒単語に分解されるからである。
 なおトークン消費量は英語文の方が日本語文よりも少ない。生成AIでは1回のやりとりで利用可能なトークン消費量に上限があるため、トークン消費量がより少ない英語文で質問した方がより長い質問が可能となる。また英語文での回答の方がより詳細な回答が一般的には生成される。

 

 そうしたことが実際にどうであるのかに関して、「原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開」という日本語で与えた場合と、”Historical Development of Arguments for and against Civilian/Non-Military Use of Nuclear power”という英語文で与えた場合の具体例は下記の通りである。
Perplexity AIでは、日本語プロンプト文では日本語の文献資料があった場合には日本語の文献資料を、英語プロンプト文では英語の文献資料を利用しながら回答を生成する設計になっているようである。
 なお下記サンプル例に見られるように、英語での回答の方がより情報量の多い回答になっている。

 
【注】

  1. 同じPerplexity AIであるが、テキスト生成エンジンが異なると、回答が下記のようにかなり異なる。GPT4o版の本回答の方が、Claude 3 Opus版よりも数多くの資料を挙げており、より情報量の多い回答となった。
     ただし、Open AIのChatGPT-4oによる回答との比較では、残念ながらOpen AIのChatGPT-4oの方がより優れた回答である。

  2. 「原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開」という題目に関連する研究が日本では相対的に少ないことを反映し、日本語プロンプト文で挙げられている14個の参考資料の内、筆者関連以外のものは3個しかない。こうした結果となったのは、回答の生成に際して特段の指示を出した結果ではない。https://www.perplexity.ai/search/.TtaEmnQSz2SMIoHB4FnBQ#0に示されているように、新しいスレッドの中で、単に「原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開」という語句をプロンプト文として与えた結果に過ぎない。
     なお「英語で書かれた参考資料を教えて下さい。」という追加のプロンプト文の結果は、下記WEBページの通りである。

 
  1. 日本語プロンプト文に対するPerplexity AI – GPT4o版による回答例(1)
  2. 英語プロンプト文に対するPerplexity AI – GPT4o版による回答例(1)
日本語プロンプト文に対するPerplexity AI-GPT4o版による回答例(1)
 
原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開についての研究は、原子力技術の発展とその社会的受容に関する多角的な視点から行われています。以下にその概要を示します。

 
研究の背景と目的

この研究は、原子力の社会的利用に関する推進論と批判論の歴史的展開を明らかにすることを目的としています。具体的には、原子物理学、原子力工学、原子力技術史、エネルギー問題、公害・環境問題、地球温暖化問題などの視点から、原子力発電所および関連施設における重大事故(スリーマイル島、チェルノブイリ、福島第一原発事故など)や原発の経済性・営利性に関する議論の歴史的展開を分析します[1][2]。

 
研究の進展と成果
資料収集とデジタル化

研究の一環として、関連資料・文献の収集とスキャニング、OCR処理による全文検索可能なデジタル資料化が行われています。これにより、研究成果のオープンアクセス化が進められ、研究室のウェブページを通じて公開されています[1][2]。

歴史的展開の分析

20世紀中の原子力利用に関する推進論と批判論の歴史的展開については、日本科学史学会技術史分科会発行の雑誌『技術史』において包括的に紹介されています。これには、「原子力発電実用化前の原子力利用推進論」や「技術史・技術論視点から見た原子力発電文献ガイド」などが含まれます[1][2]。

福島原発事故以後の変化

現在の研究では、福島原発事故以後の原子力発電をめぐる論争点の変化や、原子炉の小型化による相対的な安全化、原子炉の長寿命化を目指す次世代原発論などの問題が取り上げられています。これにより、原子力発電をめぐる擁護論と反対論の現代的展開が分析されています[1][2]。

 
具体的な研究内容
原子力の「軍事」的利用と「産業」的利用

20世紀前半における原子力の社会的利用推進論は、軍事的利用と産業的利用という二重性を持っていました。被爆国日本における原発の社会的受容に関しては、科学・技術の「善用・悪用」二元論が重要な役割を果たしました[3][5]。

アメリカの核戦略と日本の原子力開発

アメリカの核戦略の下で、日本の原子力開発政策は政治主導で進められ、科学者の自主性が軽視される傾向がありました。これにより、原子力開発の解禁とともに、政財界の現実路線が優先されるようになりました[3][5]。

経済性と安全性のバランス

原子力技術の形成においては、経済性と安全性のバランスが重要な課題となりました。これにより、原子力発電の社会的普及プロセスが進展し、社会的投資が促進されるための正当化論が展開されました[3][5][14]。

 
結論

原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開は、技術的、経済的、社会的な多角的視点からの分析が必要です。これにより、原子力発電の現代的な課題や将来の展望についての理解が深まります。

 

Citations:
[1] 佐野正博「原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開」(KAKENHI-PROJECT-16K01168)国立情報学研究所『科学研究費助成事業データベース』
https://kaken.nii.ac.jp/ja/grant/KAKENHI-PROJECT-16K01168/
[2] 「佐野 正博 (Masahiro Sano) – 原子力の社会的利用をめぐる推進論と批判論の歴史的展開 日本学術振興会 科学研究費助成事業」科学技術振興機構『researchmap』マイポータル
https://researchmap.jp/sanomshr/research_projects/45024157
[3] 原発史研究会編『日本における原子力発電のあゆみとフクシマ』に関する晃洋書房の紹介ページ
https://www.koyoshobo.co.jp/book/b355343.html
[4] 石田雄(2012)「原発事故で痛感させられた社会科学者の社会的責任-何をどうぶんせきするか」【特別寄稿】福島原発事故から考える日本の社会問題『大原社会問題研究所雑誌』641、pp.1-9
http://oisr-org.ws.hosei.ac.jp/images/oz/contents/641-01.pdf
[5] 日本における原子力発電のあゆみとフクシマ | 東京工業大学附属図書館 蔵書検索
https://topics.libra.titech.ac.jp/recordID/catalog.bib/BB2581890X?caller=xc-search&hit=9
[6] 吉岡斉(2011)『新版 原子力の社会史-その日本的展開』朝日選書
https://www.amazon.co.jp/新版-原子力の社会史-その日本的展開-朝日選書-吉岡-斉/dp/4022599839
[7] 青水司(2019)「原発と「科学・技術至上主義」批判-科学・技術の二面性の視角から」『大阪経大論集』70(1),pp.71-90
https://www.i-repository.net/il/user_contents/02/G0000031Repository/repository/keidaironshu_070_001_71-90.pdf
[8] 「佐野 正博 (Masahiro Sano) – 原子力の社会的利用推進論の20世紀前半における歴史的展開」科学技術振興機構『researchmap』マイポータル- 論文
https://researchmap.jp/sanomshr/published_papers/33414286
[9] 「佐野正博 2018 年度 実施状況報告書」国立情報学研究所『科学研究費助成事業データベース』(KAKENHI-PROJECT-16K01168)
https://kaken.nii.ac.jp/ja/report/KAKENHI-PROJECT-16K01168/16K011682018hokoku/
[10]佐野正博「原子力に関する社会的イメージの歴史的形成」『学術の動向』2014年3月号,pp.56-59
https://www.jstage.jst.go.jp/article/tits/19/3/19_3_56/_pdf
[11] 「Sano Masahiro」科学技術振興機構『J-GLOBAL』掲載 研究者情報 英語版ページ
https://jglobal.jst.go.jp/en/detail?JGLOBAL_ID=200901041463056672
[12] 慶應義塾大学図書館検索システム-原発史研究会『日本における原子力発電のあゆみとフクシマ』
[13] 原発史研究会『日本における原子力発電のあゆみとフクシマ』
[14] 兵藤友博、佐野正博、横田陽子、田中光彦、木本忠昭(2014)「公開シンポジウム報告「原子力発電の社会的普及プロセスの歴史的検討」」『科学史研究』53(269),pp.107-110
https://www.jstage.jst.go.jp/article/jhsj/53/269/53_107/_pdf

 
 

英語プロンプト文に対するPerplexity AI-GPT4o版による回答例(1)

The historical development of arguments for and against the civilian or non-military use of nuclear power has evolved significantly since the end of World War II. This evolution can be traced through various phases, reflecting changes in technological capabilities, political contexts, and public perceptions.

 
Early Enthusiasm and Legislative Foundations (1940s-1950s)
Proponents’ Arguments

After World War II, there was significant enthusiasm for the peaceful applications of nuclear energy. The Atomic Energy Act of 1946 marked a pivotal moment by transferring control of nuclear technology from military to civilian hands, establishing the Atomic Energy Commission (AEC) to oversee both military and civilian uses of nuclear energy[3][7]. Proponents argued that nuclear power could revolutionize energy production, offering a virtually limitless and clean energy source. President Dwight D. Eisenhower’s “Atoms for Peace” speech in 1953 encapsulated this optimism, suggesting that nuclear energy could be a boon for humanity if harnessed for peaceful purposes[1][10].

Opponents’ Concerns

Despite the optimism, there were early concerns about the potential risks associated with nuclear power. Critics worried about the safety of nuclear reactors, the potential for accidents, and the long-term management of radioactive waste. The Atomic Energy Act of 1954, which aimed to promote the commercial use of nuclear power, also included provisions for public health and safety, reflecting these concerns[1][11].

 
Expansion and Controversy (1960s-1980s)
Proponents’ Arguments

During the 1960s and 1970s, nuclear power was seen as a solution to the growing energy demands and a way to reduce dependence on fossil fuels. The construction of numerous nuclear power plants during this period was driven by the belief that nuclear energy could provide a stable and reliable source of electricity. Proponents highlighted the environmental benefits of nuclear power, particularly its low greenhouse gas emissions compared to coal and oil[2][4].

Opponents’ Concerns

However, the expansion of nuclear power also sparked significant opposition. The anti-nuclear movement gained momentum, particularly after high-profile accidents such as the Three Mile Island incident in 1979 and the Chernobyl disaster in 1986. These events underscored the potential for catastrophic accidents and heightened public fears about nuclear safety. Critics also pointed to the high costs and long construction times of nuclear plants, as well as the unresolved issue of nuclear waste disposal[2][6][8].

 
Renewed Interest and Ongoing Debate (1990s-Present)
Proponents’ Arguments

In recent decades, the debate over nuclear power has been influenced by concerns about climate change and the need for low-carbon energy sources. Proponents argue that nuclear power is essential for reducing carbon emissions and achieving energy security. They emphasize the advancements in reactor technology that have improved safety and efficiency, and they advocate for the use of nuclear power as part of a diversified energy strategy to combat global warming[4][10].

Opponents’ Concerns

Despite these arguments, opposition to nuclear power remains strong. Critics continue to highlight the risks of nuclear accidents, the challenges of radioactive waste management, and the potential for nuclear proliferation. They argue that the high costs and long lead times for building new nuclear plants make it an impractical solution compared to renewable energy sources like wind and solar power. Additionally, concerns about the security of nuclear facilities and the potential for terrorist attacks add to the opposition[4][6][9].

 
Conclusion

The historical development of arguments for and against the civilian use of nuclear power reflects a complex interplay of technological, political, and social factors. While nuclear power has the potential to provide significant environmental and energy security benefits, it also poses substantial risks and challenges that continue to fuel a vigorous and ongoing debate.

 

Citations:
[1] Walker,J. S., Wellock, T. R. (2010) “A Short History of Nuclear Regulation,1946–2009” NUREG/BR-0175, Rev.2
https://www.nrc.gov/docs/ML1029/ML102980443.pdf
[2] Pope, D. (2021) “The Unkept Promise of Nuclear Power”
https://origins.osu.edu/article/unkept-promise-nuclear-power?language_content_entity=en
[3] Hinnershitz, Stephanie (2021) “The Atomic Energy Act of 1946 – Scientists became political activists in the debate over control of atomic energy.” August 4, 2021
https://www.nationalww2museum.org/war/articles/atomic-energy-act-1946
[4] Wikipedia “Nuclear power debate”https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Nuclear_power_debate
[5] Sico van der Meer (2016) “States’ Motivations to Acquire or Forgo Nuclear Weapons: Four Factors of Influence,” Journal of Military and Strategic Studies, 17(1), pp.209-236 https://www.clingendael.org/sites/default/files/2018-02/States’_Motivations_to_Acquire_or_Forgo_Nuclear_Weapons _August_2016.pdf
[6] Rothwell, S. L. “antinuclear movement” Britannica.com
https://www.britannica.com/topic/anti-nuclear-movement
[7] U.S. Department of Energy “Civilian Control of Atomic Energy, 1945-1946” The Manhattan Project – an interactive history
https://www.osti.gov/opennet/manhattan-project-history/Events/1945-present/civilian_control.htm
[8] Rizvi,O.(2023) “Nuclear energy in Europe: Who is for and against it and why?” 2023 /12/23
https://link.springer.com/content/pdf/10.1007/978-3-658-25987-7_5.pdf
[9] Energy Advisory Group of the Working Committee on Church and Society, World Council of Churches, Geneva, Switzerland (1977) “Public Acceptance of Nuclear Power – Some Ethical Issues” IAEA Bulletin, 19(6), pp.48-57
https://www.iaea.org/sites/default/files/publications/magazines/bulletin/bull19-6/19604794857.pdf
This paper was presented at the International Conference on Nuclear Power and Its Fuel Cycle, 2-13 May 1977, Salzburg, Austria.
[10] World Nuclear Association(2024) “Outline History of Nuclear Energy”
https://world-nuclear.org/information-library/current-and-future-generation/outline-history-of-nuclear-energy
[11] U.S. Department of Energy The History of Nuclear Energy, Office of Nuclear Energy, Science and Technology,DOE/NE-0088, 48pp
https://www.energy.gov/ne/articles/history-nuclear-energy
[12] Bonev, P. et al. (2024) “Nuclear waste in my backyard: Social acceptance and economic incentives,” Energy Policy,185(February 2024)
https://www.nids.mod.go.jp/english/event/symposium/pdf/2001/sympo_e2001_4.pdf
[13] Hill, J. (1977) “The Abuse of Nuclear Power”IAEA Bulletin, 19(2), pp.42-49
https://www.iaea.org/sites/default/files/publications/magazines/bulletin/bull19-2/19204794249.pdf
[14] “50 Years of Nuclear Energy” 8pp
https://www.iaea.org/sites/default/files/gc/gc48inf-4-att3_en.pdf
[15] Goldschmidt, B. (1977) “The Origins of the International Atomic Energy Agency” IAEA Bulletin, 19(4), pp.12-19
https://www.iaea.org/sites/default/files/publications/magazines/bulletin/bull19-4/19401281219.pdf
[16] Ichimasa, S. (2017) “Nuclear Nonproliferation and Economic Sanctions: Can Non-Military Sanctions Stop Nuclear Proliferation? ” 防衛研究所紀要(防衛省防衛研究所)、19(2)
https://www.nids.mod.go.jp/english/publication/kiyo/pdf/2017/bulletin_e2017_4.pdf (日本語版一政祐行(2017)「核不拡散と経済制裁を巡る諸問題」)
[17] Office of the Historian, Foreign Service Institute, United States Department of State “MILESTONES: 1945–1952 Atomic Diplomacy” Milestones in the History of U.S. Foreign Relations
https://history.state.gov/milestones/1945-1952/atomic
[18] Campaign for Nuclear Disarmament “The history of CND”
https://cnduk.org/who/the-history-of-cnd/
[19] Clarke, L. (1985) “The Origins of Nuclear Power: A Case of Institutional Conflict” Social Problems, 32(5), pp.474-487
https://www.jstor.org/stable/800776
[20] Char,N.L., Csik, B.J. (1987) “Nuclear power development:History and outlook – Events have changed the global prospects for nuclear power,” IAEA BULLETIN, 3/1987, pp.19-25
https://www.jstor.org/stable/40961953

カテゴリー: レポート作成, 原子力の平和的利用, 日本語プロンプトvs英語プロンプト, 生成AIの利用法 | コメントする

生成AIでの情報検索-移民問題(日本語プロンプト版)

生成AIは、Google検索などこれまでのWEB検索サービスの機能拡張、すなわち、拡張検索エンジンとして利用することができます。ここでは、移民問題に関する情報検索を例に取り、情報検索の効率化が生成AIによってどのように実現できるかを見ていきましょう。

 
利用したプロンプト文(日本語)
英語で移民問題を調べたい。
おすすめの検索ワードを教えて。
 
生成AIの回答例

 
生成AI利用における注意点
  1. まったく同一のプロンプト文を生成AIに繰り返し与えると、生成AIはその都度、異なる回答を返すような設計にデフォルトではなっています。まったく同じ質問を同じ人にくり返した場合でも、知識の引き出しが大きく親切な人であればそれまでとは異なる回答を返して、質問者の理解をより深めるようにしてくれるのと同じです。
     下記では各生成AIの回答を一例だけしか挙げていませんが、実際の情報検索に当たっては、同一のAIに対して回答のバリエーションがなくなるまで同じ質問を繰り返すことでより多くの情報を得ることができます。
     

  2. プロンプト文がまったく同一であっても、各生成AIによってその回答には「個性」やバラツキがあります。まったく同じ質問を数多くの人にした場合に、回答者のものの見方考え方、個性、知識量の違いにより様々な回答が返ってくるのと同じです。
     生成AIにも、「利用している生成エンジンのLLM(Large Language Models、大規模言語モデル)」、「回答生成に利用しているデータ」、「回答生成の際のパラメーター」などの違いにより、「ものの見方考え方」、「個性」、「知識量」の違いがあります。
     下記に挙げたように、異なるAIに対して同一の質問をすることで、結果的により適切な情報を得ることができます。
 
  1. 本ブログ記事は、藤森智世「マルチモーダルAIといっしょに英語メディアを読み解く」(連載:AI時代のアプローチ 自分仕様の英語教材をつくる 第1回)『多聴多読マガジン』2024年6月号,pp.109-114の追加・補足です。
    プロンプト文は同雑誌連載記事のものを使いましたが、生成AIによる回答結果は本ブログ記事作成時点のものです。そのため、雑誌連載記事とは少し異なった内容のものとなっています。

  2. プロンプト文全体を英語で書く方がより適切で、より詳細な回答を得ることが一般的には期待できます。プロンプト文を英語で聞いた場合の結果については別掲記事をご覧ください。
  3. ここでは無料利用版の結果のみを紹介しています。有料版の方がより適切で詳細な回答を生成することが期待できますが、月20ドルの利用料金が必要です。
カテゴリー: レポート作成, 情報検索, 日本語プロンプトvs英語プロンプト, 生成AIの利用法 | 7件のコメント

生成AIでの情報検索-移民問題(日本語プロンプト版-Perplexity AI編)

 

移民問題に関する英語の検索ワードとしては、以下のようなものがおすすめです。

## 一般的な検索ワード

  1. immigration issues
  2. immigration policies
  3. immigration laws
  4. immigration reform
  5. immigrant rights
 

## 特定の側面に焦点を当てた検索ワード

  1. undocumented immigrants
  2. refugee crisis
  3. asylum seekers
  4. family separations at the border
  5. immigrant detention centers
  6. immigrant integration
  7. immigrant assimilation
  8. immigration and employment
  9. immigration and education
  10. immigration and healthcare
 

これらのキーワードを使えば、移民問題の概要から具体的な論点まで幅広く調べられるでしょう。検索エンジンで組み合わせて使うと、より詳細な情報が見つかります[1][3]。

また、特定の国や地域に絞って検索するのも有効です。例えば “immigration in the US” や “immigration in Europe” などです。政府機関や国際機関のウェブサイトも移民統計や政策情報の貴重な情報源となります[3]。

 

下記に挙げたPerplexity AI(無料版:ChatGPT3.5)が挙げた参考資料は、そのタイトルからわかるように、参考資料3.「海外の事例に学ぶ、移民がより活躍する社会のあり方」を除くと、移民問題とは無関係なWEB記事である。
無料版Perplexity AIが用いているChatGPT3.5というテキスト生成AIエンジンは、「信頼性」よりも「創造性」や「面白さ」を優先した回答を生成するような設計になるためこのような結果になりやすい。参考資料の検索作業には、無料版Perplexity AIの利用は向かない。

Citations:

カテゴリー: 『多聴多読マガジン』連載記事, 情報検索, 生成AIの利用法, 藤森智世連載記事, 資料検索 | 1件のコメント

生成AIでの情報検索-移民問題(日本語プロンプト版-Claude AI編)

 

移民問題は多岐にわたる複雑な問題ですので、検索ワードを絞り込むことが重要です。おすすめの検索ワードは以下のようなものがあります。

  1. Immigration issues
  2. Immigration policies
  3. Immigration reform
  4. Immigration laws
  5. Immigration trends
  6. Refugee crisis
  7. Asylum seekers
  8. Undocumented immigrants
  9. Immigrant rights
  10. Immigration impact on economy/society
 

特に関心のある国や地域、具体的な側面(経済的影響、人権、安全保障など)に絞ると、より適切な情報が得られると思います。

 

例:

  1. US immigration policies
  2. European refugee crisis
  3. Economic impact of immigration in Japan
  4. Human rights of undocumented immigrants
 

検索エンジンで上記のようなキーワードを使って検索し、信頼できる政府機関、国際機関、シンクタンク、大手メディアの記事を参考にすることをおすすめします。

 
Claude AIも、ChatGPT3.5、ChatGPT4、Google Geminiと同じく、参考資料を挙げません。そのため、「有益な参考資料を挙げてください。」といった趣旨のプロンプト文を追加で与える必要があります。

そうした回答結果の一例は下記の通りです。同回答に示されているように、残念ながら、URLや資料内容に関する詳しい情報は残念ながら得ることができません。

以下、参考資料に関するClaude AIの回答
 

政府機関の報告書:
– 国連難民高等弁務官事務所(UNHCR)の年次報告書
– 国際移住機関(IOM)の世界移住報告
– 米国移民統計年鑑(Yearbook of Immigration Statistics)
– EUの移民・避難民に関する年次報告書

国際機関の報告書:
– 経済協力開発機構(OECD)の移民アウトルック(International Migration Outlook)
– 国連人口部(UN Population Division)の移住データポータル

シンクタンクの報告書:
– 移民政策研究所(MPI)の出版物
– ブルッキングス研究所の移民関連レポート
– ピュー研究所の移民に関する調査報告

学術誌:
– International Migration Review
– Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies
– Diaspora Studies

上記の機関・団体は信頼できる情報源として知られています。法的側面、経済影響、人口動態、人権など、様々な観点から移民問題を扱った資料が見つかります。関心のある特定の側面に絞って、最新の報告書や論文を参照すると良いでしょう。

カテゴリー: 『多聴多読マガジン』連載記事, 情報検索, 生成AIの利用法, 藤森智世連載記事, 資料検索 | 1件のコメント

生成AIでの情報検索-移民問題(日本語プロンプト版-Google Gemini編3)

別稿「テキスト生成AIにおける最小処理単位「トークン」ーなぜ日本語文よりも英語文の方がより詳細な回答となるのか?」で詳しく説明していますように、テキスト生成AIでは、回答文の長さには制限があります。有料版に比べ、無料版ではその制限はより厳しくなっています。そのため回答が途中で途切れることがあります。
 そうした場合には、「続きを教えてください。」などのプロンプト文を与えることで続きを見ることができます。

「移民問題」資料についての、Google Geminiの途中で途切れた回答の続きは下記の通りでした。

 
移民問題:更なる情報と考察
 
政策議論
  • 米国における移民改革: 米国では、長年、移民制度改革に関する議論が続いています。議論の争点は、不法移民の取り扱い、就労資格の拡大、家族移民の制限など多岐にわたります。
  • 欧州における移民政策: 欧州各国も、移民の流入増加に対応するため、様々な政策を講じています。政策内容は国によって様々ですが、共通の課題として、移民の受け入れと社会統合、移民排斥主義の台頭などが挙げられます。
    • 参考資料:
      • 欧州委員会: [無効な URL を削除しました]
      • ヨーロッパ政策研究センター: https://www.cepr.net/
倫理的な問題
  • 移民と人権: 移民は、差別、人身売買、搾取などの様々な人権侵害に直面するリスクが高いです。国際社会は、移民の人権保護の重要性を訴え、様々な対策を講じています。
    • 参考資料:
      • 国連人権高等弁務官事務所 (OHCHR): [無効な URL を削除しました]
      • ヒューマン・ライツ・ウォッチ: [無効な URL を削除しました]
  • 移民と文化的多様性: 移民の流入は、社会の文化的多様性を促進します。しかし、同時に、文化的な摩擦や社会の分裂を引き起こす可能性も指摘されています。
    • 参考資料:
      • 国連教育科学文化機関 (UNESCO): [無効な URL を削除しました]
      • 国際移民移住機関 (IOM): [無効な URL を削除しました]
個人の体験
  • 移民の物語: 移民問題は、統計データや政策議論だけでなく、個々人の具体的な体験を通して理解することも重要です。移民の自伝やインタビューを読むことで、移民が直面する困難や喜びをより深く理解することができます。
    • 参考資料:
      • 移民ストーリー: [無効な URL を削除しました]
      • ビヨンド・ザ・ボーダー: [無効な URL を削除しました]
日本の移民問題
  • 日本の移民政策: 日本は伝統的に移民国家ではなく、近年になってようやく外国人労働者の受け入れを拡大する政策を始めています。しかし、依然として多くの課題が残されています。
    • 参考資料:
      • 法務省出入国在留管理庁: https://www.moj.go.jp/isa/
      • 独立行政法人 国際協力機構 (JICA): [無効な URL を削除しました]
  • 日本の社会と移民: 日本の社会は、人口減少と少子高齢化が進んでいます。移民の受け入れは、日本の社会の活性化に貢献する可能性を秘めていますが、同時に、文化や価値観の違いによる摩擦や社会保障制度への負担増などの課題も指摘されています。
 

上記のように、Google Geminiが与えた続きの中には、「ヨーロッパ政策研究センター: ヨーロッパにおける移民と労働市場」に関するURLがありませんでした。
 
こうした場合には、「下記資料のURLおよび内容を教えてください。」といったようなプロンプト文を与えることで、該当資料に対するURL情報を求めることができます。
下記回答文では資料特定ができなかった旨の記載がありますが、下記の2番目の研究報告書が対応する資料です。

 
ヨーロッパ政策研究センター: ヨーロッパにおける移民と労働市場に関する追加情報
 
残念ながら、ご提示いただいた情報だけでは、特定の資料を特定することはできません。ヨーロッパ政策研究センターは、移民と労働市場に関する多くの研究報告書を発行しており、それぞれ異なるURLでアクセスできます。
 
内容
ヨーロッパ政策研究センターが発行している移民と労働市場に関する研究報告書は、内容が様々です。以下に、代表的な報告書と概要を紹介します。
  • “The impact of immigration on wages and employment in Europe” (2019): この報告書では、移民がヨーロッパの賃金と雇用に与える影響を分析しています。分析結果によると、移民は一般的に賃金を押し下げる効果はなく、むしろ一部の分野では賃金上昇に貢献していることが示されています。
    https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/bejeap-2014-0075/html?lang=en
  • “Immigration and the European labour market” (2016): この報告書では、ヨーロッパの労働市場における移民の役割を包括的に分析しています。報告書では、移民が労働力不足を補い、経済成長を促進する役割を果たしている一方で、移民排斥主義の高まりや社会統合の課題など、移民政策に関する様々な課題についても考察しています。
    https://repec.cepr.org/repec/cpr/ceprdp/DP4061.pdf
  • “The fiscal effects of immigration in Europe” (2012): この報告書では、移民がヨーロッパの財政に与える影響を分析しています。分析結果によると、移民は一般的に財政収支にプラスの影響を与え、社会保障制度への負担増加を相殺する効果があることが示されています。
    https://www.econstor.eu/bitstream/10419/232517/1/GLO-DP-0814.pdf
 
その他
上記以外にも、ヨーロッパ政策研究センターは、移民と労働市場に関する様々な研究報告書を発行しています。詳細は、以下のウェブサイトをご覧ください。
 
  • ヨーロッパ政策研究センター 移民・社会統合プログラム: https://cepr.org/
 
カテゴリー: 『多聴多読マガジン』連載記事, 情報検索, 生成AIの利用法, 藤森智世連載記事, 資料検索 | 2件のコメント

生成AIでの情報検索-移民問題(日本語プロンプト版-Google Gemini編2)

Google Geminiはデフォルト設定では、ChatGPT3.5やChatGPT4と同じく、参考資料を挙げません。そのため参考資料を知るためには、「有益な参考資料を挙げてください。」といった趣旨のプロンプト文を追加で与える必要があります。
 そうした回答結果の一例は下記の通り、Microsoft Copilotよりもかなり有益でした。この回答結果を見ると、Google Geminiは自社のGoogle検索エンジンを利用して、有益な参考資料を挙げるとともに、URLの有効・無効をチェックし、無効なURLを削除する設定になっているようです。

移民問題に関する有益な参考資料
国際機関
  • 国際連合難民高等弁務官事務所 (UNHCR): https://www.unhcr.org/
    • UNHCRは、世界中の難民や避難民を保護し、支援することを目的とした国際機関です。ウェブサイトでは、難民問題に関する統計データ、ニュース、レポートなどを公開しています。
  • 国際移住機関 (IOM): https://www.iom.int/
    • IOMは、移住に関する国際的な協力と支援を行うことを目的とした国際機関です。ウェブサイトでは、移住に関する研究、政策提言、ニュースなどを公開しています。
  • OECD: https://www.oecd.org/about/
    • OECDは、先進国を中心とした加盟国間の経済協力と発展を促進することを目的とした国際機関です。ウェブサイトでは、移民に関する統計データ、研究報告書などを公開しています。
政府機関
  • 米国移民局: https://www.uscis.gov/
    • 米国移民局は、米国への移民に関する法執行と管理を行う政府機関です。ウェブサイトでは、移民申請手続き、ビザ情報、市民権取得情報などを公開しています。
  • 法務省出入国在留管理庁: https://www.moj.go.jp/isa/
    • 法務省出入国在留管理庁は、日本への入国・在留に関する管理を行う政府機関です。ウェブサイトでは、入国・在留に関する法令、申請手続き、統計データなどを公開しています。
研究機関
  • ピーュー・リサーチ・センター: https://www.pewresearch.org/
    • ピュー・リサーチ・センターは、社会問題に関する調査や分析を行う非営利の研究機関です。ウェブサイトでは、移民問題に関する調査結果や分析記事などを公開しています。
  • Migration Policy Institute: https://www.migrationpolicy.org/
    • Migration Policy Instituteは、米国を中心とした移民政策に関する研究を行う非営利のシンクタンクです。ウェブサイトでは、研究報告書、政策提言、ニュース記事などを公開しています。
  • ヨーロッパ政策研究センター: https://www.cepr.net/
    • ヨーロッパ政策研究センターは、ヨーロッパの経済問題に関する研究を行う独立系のシンクタンクです。ウェブサイトでは、移民問題に関する研究報告書、ワーキングペーパーなどを公開しています。
ニュース
  • BBC News: https://www.bbc.com/news/world
    • BBC Newsは、英国放送協会 (BBC) が運営する国際ニュースサイトです。世界中のニュースを多角的に報道しており、移民問題に関する記事も充実しています。
  • The New York Times: https://www.nytimes.com/
    • The New York Timesは、米国で発行される世界的な日刊新聞です。移民問題に関する論説、記事、ブログなどを掲載しています。
  • The Guardian: https://www.theguardian.com/us
    • The Guardianは、英国で発行される日刊新聞です。移民問題に関する論説、記事、ブログなどを掲載しています。
その他
  • 移民問題に関する書籍: 書籍も、移民問題に関する有益な情報源です。図書館や書店で、移民問題に関する書籍を探してみましょう。
  • 移民問題に関するドキュメンタリー: ドキュメンタリー映画も、移民問題を理解するのに役立ちます。オンラインストリーミングサービスやDVDなどで、移民問題に関するドキュメンタリーを探してみましょう。
上記以外にも、移民問題に関する情報は数多く存在します。 自分に合った情報源を見つけて、移民問題について理解を深めていきましょう。
 
以下、参考となる具体的な資料を紹介します。
 
統計データ
研究報告書
カテゴリー: 『多聴多読マガジン』連載記事, 情報検索, 生成AIの利用法, 藤森智世連載記事, 資料検索 | 2件のコメント

生成AIでの情報検索-移民問題(日本語プロンプト版- Microsoft Copilot編)

 
利用したプロンプト文(日本語)
英語で移民問題を調べたい。
おすすめの検索ワードを教えて。
 
Microsoft Copilot(無料版)による回答
移民問題に関する英語の検索ワードとしては、以下のようなものがあります:

  1. Immigration policies – 移民政策
  2. Refugee crisis – 難民危機
  3. Border security – 国境警備
  4. Economic impact of immigration – 移民の経済的影響
  5. Cultural integration – 文化的統合
  6. Legal immigration – 合法移民
  7. Unauthorized immigration – 不法移民
  8. Asylum seekers – 亡命希望者
  9. Immigration reform – 移民改革
  10. Migrant workers – 移民労働者
 

これらのキーワードを使用して、移民問題に関する情報を幅広く検索することができます。特定の国や地域に関する情報を探している場合は、国名や地域名をキーワードに追加すると良いでしょう。例えば、「US immigration issues」や「Japan immigration news」などです。¹²

 

また、移民問題に関する最新の研究やデータを探している場合は、Pew Research CenterNikkei Asiaなどの信頼できる情報源を参照すると良いでしょう。¹,² これらのサイトでは、移民問題に関する深い分析や統計データが提供されています。幅広い視点から移民問題を理解するために役立つでしょう。

 

ソース: Copilot との会話、 2024/6/17

  1. Immigration Issues | Pew Research Center.
    https://www.pewresearch.org/topic/immigration-migration/immigration-issues
  2. Japan immigration: News & Insights – Nikkei Asia.
    https://asia.nikkei.com/Spotlight/Japan-immigration
  3. Immigration issuesの意味・使い方・読み方 | Weblio英和辞書.
    https://ejje.weblio.jp/content/Immigration+issue
  4. Ten Graphics That Explain the U.S. Struggle With Migrant ….
    https://www.cfr.org/article/ten-graphics-explain-us-struggle-migrant-flows-2022
  5. Immigration & Migration | Pew Research Center.
    https://www.pewresearch.org/topic/immigration-migration
カテゴリー: 『多聴多読マガジン』連載記事, 情報検索, 生成AIの利用法, 藤森智世連載記事 | 1件のコメント